Manifesto of the Communist Party
A spectre is haunting europe - the spectre
of Communism. All the powers of old Europe
have entered into a holy alliance to exorcise
this spectre; Pope and Czar, Metternich and
Guizot, French Radicals and German police-
spies.
Where is the party in opposition that has
not been decried as communistic by its opponents
in power? Where the opposition that
has not hurled back the branding reproach
of Communism, against the more advanced
opposition parties, as well as against its
reactionary adversaries?
Two things result from this fact.
I. Communism is already acknowledged
by all European Powers to be itself a Power.
II. It is high time that Communists should
openly, in the face of the whole world, publish
their views, their aims, their tendencies,
and meet this nursery tale of the Spectre of
Communism with a Manifesto of the party
itself.
To this end, Communists of various nationalities
have assembled in London, and
sketched the following manifesto, to be published
in the English, French, German, Italian,
Flemish and Danish languages.
I
Bourgeois and Proletarians
The history of all hitherto existing society
is the history of class struggles.
Freeman and slave, patrician and plebeian,
lord and serf, guild-master and journeyman,
in a word; oppressor and oppressed, stood in
constant opposition to one another, carried
on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open
fight, a fight that each time has ended, either in
a revolutionary re-constitution of society at
large, or in the common ruin of the contending
classes.
In the early epochs of history, we find almost
everywhere a complicated arrangement
of society into various orders, a manifold
graduation of social rank. In ancient Rome
we have patricians, knights, plebeians, slaves;
in the Middle Ages, feudal lords, vassals,
guild-masters, journeymen, apprentices, serfs;
in almost all of these classes, again, subordinate
graduations.
The modern bourgeois society that has
sprouted from the ruins of feudal society. has
not done away with class antagonisms. It has
but established new classes, new conditions
of oppression, new forms of struggle in place
of the old ones.
Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeoisie,
possesses, however, this distinctive feature;
it has simplified the class antagonisms.
Society as a whole is more and more splitting
up into two great hostile camps, into two
great classes directly facing each other: Bourgeoisie
and Proletariat.
From the serfs of the Middle Ages sprang
the chartered burghers of the earliest towns.
From these burgesses the first elements of the
bourgeoisie were developed.
The discovery of America, the rounding of
the Cape, opened up fresh ground for the
rising bourgeoisie. The East-Indian and Chinese
markets, the colonization of America,
trade with the colonies, the increase in the
means of exchange and in commodities, generally,
gave to commerce, to navigation, to
industry, an impulse never before known,
and thereby, to the revolutionary element in
the tottering feudal society, a rapid development.
The feudal system of industry, under which
industrial production was monopolized by
closed guilds, now no longer sufficed for the
growing wants of the markets. The manufacturing
system took its place. The guild-
masters were pushed on one side by the
manufacturing middle-class; division of labor
between the different corporate guilds vanished
in the face of division of labor in each
single workshop.
Meantime the markets kept ever growing,
the demand, ever rising. Even manufacturing
no longer sufficed. Thereupon, steam and
machinery revolutionized industrial production.
The place of manufacture was taken by
the giant, Modern Industry, the place of the
industrial middle-class, by industrial millionaires,
the leaders of whole industrial armies,
the modern bourgeoisie.
Modern Industry has established the
world-market, for which the discover of
America paved the way. This market has
given an immense development to commerce,
to navigation, to communication by land.
This develpoment has, in its turn, reacted on
the extension of industry,; and in proportion
as industry, commerce, navigation, railways
extended in the same proportion the bourgeoisie
developed, increased its capital, and
pushed into the background every class
handed down from the Middle Ages.
We see, therefore, how the modern bourgeoisie
is itself the product of a long course
of development, of a series of revolutions in
the modes of production and of exchange.
Each step in the devlopment of the bougeoisie
was accompanied by a corresponding
political advance of that class. An oppressed
class under the sway of the feudal nobility,
an armed and self-governing association in
the medieval commune, here independent
urban republic (as in Italy and Germany),
there taxable "third estate" of the monarchy
(as in France), afterwards, in the period of
manufacturing proper, serving either the
semi-feudal or the absolute monarchy as a
counterpoise against the nobility, and in fact,
cornerstone of the great monarchies in general,
the bougeoisie has at last, since the
establishment of Modern Industry and of the
world-market, conquered for itself, in the
modern respresentative State, exclusive political
sawy. The executive of the modern State
is but a committee for managing the common
affairs of the whole bourgeoisie.
The bougeoisie, historically, has played
a most revolutionary part.
The bougeoisie, wherever it has got the
upper hand, has put an end to all feudal,
patriarchal, idyllic relations. It has pitilessly
torn assunder the motley feudal ties that
bound man to his "natural superiors," and
has left remaining no other nexus between
man and man than naked self-interest, than
callous "cash payment." It has drowned the
most heavenly ecstasies of religious fervor,
of chivalrous euthasiasm, of philistine sentimentalism,
in the icy water of egotistical calculation.
it has resolved personal worth into
exchange value, and in place of the number-
less indefeasible chartered freedoms, has set
up that single, unconscionable freedom - Free
Trade. In one word, for exploitation, veiled
by religious and political illusions, it has substituted
naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation.
The bourgeoisie has stripped of its halo
every occupation hitherto honored and
looked up to with reverant awe. It has converted
the physician, the lawyer, the priest,
the poet, the man of science, into its paid
wage-laborers.
The bourgeoisie has torn away from the
family its setimental veil, and has reduced
the family relation to a mere money relation.
The bougeoisie has discovered how it came
to pass that the brutal display of vigor in the
Middle Ages, which Reactionists so much admire,
found its fitting complement in the
most slothful indolence. It has been the first
to show what man's activity an bring about.
It has accomplished wonders far surpassing
Egyptian pyramids, Roman aqueducts, and
Gothic cathedrals; it has conducted expeditions
that put in the shade all former Exoduses
of nations and crusades.
The bourgeoisie cannot exist without constantly
revolutionizing the instruments of
production, and thereby the relations of production,
and with them the whole relations
of society. Conversation of the old modes of
production in unaltered form, was, on the
contrary, the first condition of existence for
all earlier industrial classes. Constant revolutionizing
of production, uninterrupted disturbance
of all social conditions, everlasting
uncertainty and agitation distinguish the
bourgeois epoch from all earlier ones. All
fixed, fast-frozen relations, with their train
of ancient and venerable prejudices and
opinions, are swept away, all newly-formed
ones become antiquated before they can
ossify. All that is solid melts into air, all that
is holy is profaned, and man is at last compelled
to face with sober senses, his real conditions
of life, and his relations with his kind.
The need of a constantly expanding market
for its products chases the bourgeoisie over
the whole surface of the globe. It must nestle
everywhere, settle everywhere, establish connections
everywhere.
The bourgeoisie has, through its exploitation
of the world-market, given a cosmopolitan
character to production and consumption in
every country. To the great chagrin of Reactionaries,
it has drawn from under the feet
of industry the national ground on which it
stood. All old-established national industries
have been destroyed or are daily being destroyed.
They are dislodged by new industries,
whose introduction becomes a life and
death question for all civilized nations, by
industries that no longer work up indigenous
raw material, but raw material drawn from
the remotest zones; industries whose products
are consumed, not only at home, but in every
quarter of the globe. In place of the old
wants, satisfied by the productions of the
country, we find new wants, requiring for
their satisfaction the products of distant lands
and climes. In place of the old local and national
seclusion and self-sufficiency, we have
intercourse in every direction, universal
inter-dependence of nations. And as in material, so
also in intellectual production. The
intellectual creations of individual nations become
common property. National one-sidedness
and narrow-mindedness become more
and more impossible, and from the numerous
national and local literatures there arises a
world literature.
The bourgeoisie, by the rapid improvement
of all instruments of production, by the immensely
facilitated means of communication,
draws all, even the most barbarian, nations
into civilization. The cheap prices of commodities
are the heavy artillery with which it
forces the barbarians' intensely obstinate hatred
of foreigners to capitulate. It compels all
nations, on pain of extinction, to adopt the
bourgeois mode of production; it compels
them to introduce what it calls civilization
into their midst, i.e., to become bourgeois
themselves. In one word, it creates a world after
its own image.
The bourgeoisie has subjected the country
to the rule of the towns. It has created enormous
cities, has greatly increased the urban
population as compared with the rural, and
has thus rescued a considerable part of
the population from the idiocy of rural life. Just
as it has made the country dependent on the
towns, so it has made barbarian and semi-barbarian
countries dependent on the civilized
ones, nations of peasants on nations of
bourgeois, the East on the West.
The bourgeoisie keeps more and more doing
away with the scattered state of the population,
of the means of production, and of
property. It has agglomerated population,
centralized the means of production, and has concentrated
property in a few hands. The necessary
consequence of this was political centralization.
Independent, or but loosely connected
provinces, with separate interests,
laws, governments, and systems of taxation,
became lumped together into one nation, with
one government, one code of laws, one national
class-interest, one frontier, and one customs-tariff.
The bourgeoisie, during its rule of scarce
one hundred years, has created more massive
and more colossal productive forces than
have all preceding generations together. Subjection
of Nature's forces to man, machinery,
application of chemistry to industry and agriculture,
steam-navigation, railways, electric
telegraphs, clearing of whole continents for
cultivation, canalization of rivers, whole populations
conjured out of the ground - what
earlier century had even a presentiment that
such productive forces slumbered in the lap
of social labor?
We see then: the means of production and
of exchange, on whose foundation the bourgeoisie
built itself up, were generated in
feudal society. At a certain stage in the development
of these means of production and
of exchange, the conditions under which
feudal society produced and exchanged, the
feudal organization of agriculture and manufacturing
industry, in one word, the feudal
relations of property became no longer compatible
with the already developed productive
forces; they became so many fetters.
They had to be burst asunder; they were
burst asunder.
Into their place stepped free competition,
accompanied by a social and political constitution
adapted to it, and by the economical
and political sway of the bourgeois class.
A similar movement is going on before our
own eyes. Modern bourgeois society, with its
relations of production, of exchange and of
property, a society that has conjured up such
gigantic means of production and of exchange,
is like the sorcerer, who is no longer
able to control the power of the nether world
whom he has called up by his spells. For
many a decade past the history of industry
and commerce is but the history of the revolt
of modern productive forces against modern
conditions of production, against the property
relations that are the condition for the existence
of the bourgeoisie and of its rule. It is
enough to mention the commercial crises that
by their periodical return put on trial, each
time more threateningly, the existence of the
entire bourgeios society. In these crises a
great part not only of the existing products,
but also of the previously created productive
forces, are periodically destroyed. In these
crises there breaks out an epidemic that, in
all earlier epochs, would have seemed an absurdity
- the epidemic of over-production.
Society suddenly finds itself put back into a
state of momentary barbarism; it appears as if
a famine, a universal war of devastation had
cut off the supply of every means of subsistence;
industry and commerce seem to be destroyed;
and why? Because there is too much
civilization, too much means of subsistence,
too much industry, too much commerce. The
productive forces at the disposal of society no
longer tend to further the development of
the conditions of bourgeois property; on the
contrary, they have become too powerful for
these conditions, by which they are fettered,
and so soon as they overcome these fetters,
they bring disorder into the whole of bourgeois
society, endangering the existence of
bourgeois property. The conditions of bourgeois
society are too narrow to comprise the
wealth created by them. And how does the
bourgeoisie get over these crises? One the one
hand by enforced destruction of a mass of
productive forces; on the other, by the conquest
of new markets, and by the more thorough
exploitation of the old ones. That is to
say, by paving the way for more extensive
and more destructive crises, and by diminishing
the means whereby crises are prevented.
The weapons with which the bourgeoisie
felled feudalism to the ground are now
turned against the bourgeoisie itself.
But not only has the bourgeoisie forged the
weapons that bring death to itself; it has also
called into existence the men who are to
wield those weapons - the modern working-class
- the proletarians.
In proportion as the bourgeoisie, i.e., capital,
is developed, in the same proportion is
the proletariat, the modern working-class, developed,
a class of laborers, who live only so
long as they find work, and who find work
only so long as their labor increases capital.
These laborers, who must sell themselves
piecemeal, are a commodity, like every other
article of commerce, and are consequently
exposed to all the vicissitudes of competition,
to all the fluctuations of the market.
Owing to the extensive use of machinery
and to division of labor, the work of the proletarians
has lost all individual character, and,
consequently, all charm for the workman. He
becomes an appendage of the machine, and
it is only the most simple, most monotonous,
and most easily acquired knack that is required
of him. Hence, the cost of production
of a workman is restricted, almost entirely,
to the means of subsistence that he requires
for his maintenance, and for the propagation
of his race. But the price of a commodity, and
also of labor, is equal to its cost of production.
In proportion, therefore, as the repulsiveness
of the work increases, the wage decreases.
Nay more, in proportion as the use of machinery
and division of labor increases, in the
same proportion the burden of toil also increases,
whether by prolongation of the working
hours, by increase of the work enacted
in a given time, or by increased speed of the
machinery, etc.
Modern Industry has converted the little
workshop of the patriarchal master into the
great factory of the industrial capitalist.
Masses of laborers, crowded into the factory,
are organized like soldiers. As privates of the
industrial army they are placed under the
command of a perfect hierarchy of officers
and sergeants. Not only are they slaves
of the bourgeois class, and of the bourgeois
State, they are daily and hourly enslaved by
the machine, by the over-looker, and, above
all, by the individual bourgeois manufacturer
himself. The more openly this despotism proclaims
gain to be its end and aim, the more
petty, the more hateful and the more embittering
it is.
The less the skill and exertion of strength
implied in manual labor, in other words, the
more modern industry becomes developed,
the more is the labor of men superseded by
that of women. Differences of age and sex
have no longer any distinctive social validity
for the working class.All are instruments of
labor, more or less expensive to use, according
to their age and sex.
No sooner is the exploitation of the laborer
by the manufacturer, so far at an end, that
he receives his wages in cash, than he is set
upon by the other portions of the bourgeoisie,
the landlord, the shopkeeper, the pawnbroker,
etc.
The low strata of the middle class - the
small tradespeople, shopkeepers, and retired
tradesmen generally, the handicraftsmen and
peasants - all these sink gradually into the
proletariat, partly because their diminutive
capital does not suffice for the scale on which
Modern Industry is carried on, and is
swamped in the competition with the large
capitalists, partly because their specialized
skill is rendered worthless by new methods
of production. Thus, the proletariat is recruited
from all classes of the population.
The proletariat goes through various stages
of development. With its birth begins its
struggle with the bourgeoisie. At first the
contest is carried on by individual laborers,
then by the workpeople of a factory, then by
the operative of one trade, in one locality,
against the individual bourgeois who directly
exploits them. They direct their attacks not
against the bourgeois conditions of production,
but against the instruments of production
themselves; they destroy imported wares
that compete with their labor, they smash to
pieces machinery, they set factories ablaze,
they seek to restore by force the vanished
status of the workman of the Middle Ages.
At this stage, the laborers still form an incoherent
mass scattered over the whole country,
and broken up by their mutual competition.
If anywhere they unite to form more
compact bodies, this is not yet the consequence
of their own active union, but of the
union of the bourgeoisie, which class, in order to
attain its own political ends, is compelled to
set the whole proletariat in motion, and is
moreover yet, for a time, able to do so. At
this stage, therefore, the proletarians do not
fight their enemies, but the enemies of their
enemies, the remnants of absolute monarchy,
the landowners, the non-industrial bourgeoisie,
the petty bourgeois. Thus the whole
historical movement is concentrated in the
hands of the bourgeoisie; every victory so obtained
is a victory for the bourgeoisie.
But with the development of industry the
proletariat not only increases in number, it
becomes concentrated in great masses, its
strength grows, and it feels that strength
more. The various interests and conditions of
life within the ranks of the proletariat are more
and more equalized, in proportion as machinery
obliterates all distinction of labor,
and nearly everywhere reduces wages to the
same low level. The growing competition
among the bourgeoisie, and the resulting
commercial crises, make the wages of the
worker ever more fluctuating. The unceasing
improvement of machinery, ever more rapidly
developing, makes their livelihood more and
more precarious; the collisions between individual
workmen and individual bourgeois
take more and more the character of collision
between two classes. Thereupon the workers
begin to form combinations (Trade Unions)
against the bourgeois; they club together in
order to keep up the rate of wages; they
found permanent associations in order to
make provision beforehand for these occasional
revolts. Here and there the contest
breaks out into riots.
Now and then the workers are victorious,
but only for a time. The real fruit of their
battles lie, not in the immediate result, but
in the ever expanding union of the workers.
This union is helped on by the improved
means of communication that are created by
modern industry, and that place the workers
of different localities in contact with one another.
It was just this contact that was needed
to centralize the numerous local struggles, all
of the same character, into one national struggle
between classes. But every class struggle
is a political struggle. And that union, to attain
which the burghers of the Middle Ages,
with their miserable highways, required centuries,
the modern proletarians, thanks to railways,
achieve in a few years.
This organization of the proletarians into a
class, and consequently into a political party,
is continually being upset again by the competition
between the workers themselves. But
it ever rises up again, stronger, firmer,
mightier. It compels legislative recognition of
particular interests of the workers, by taking
advantage of the divisions among the bourgeoisie
itself. Thus the ten-hour bill in England
was carried.
Altogether, collisions between the classes
of the old society further, in many ways, the
course of development of the proletariat. The
bourgeoisie finds itself involved in a constant
battle. At first with the aristocracy; later on,
with those portions of the bourgeoisie itself,
whose interests have become antagonistic to
the progress of industry; at all time, with the
bourgeoisie of foreign countries. In all these
battles, it sees itself compelled to appeal to
the proletariat, to ask for its help, and thus,
to drag it into the political arena. The bourgeoisie
itself, therefore, supplies the proletariat
with its own elements of political and
general education, in other words, it furnishes
the proletariat with weapons for fighting the
bourgeoisie.
Further, as we have already seen, entire
sections of the ruling classes are, by the advance
of industry, precipitated into the proletariat,
or are at least threatened in their conditions
of existence. These also supply the
proletariat with fresh elements of enlightenment
and progress.
Finally, in times when the class-struggle
nears the decisive hour, the progress of dissolution
going on within the ruling class, in fact
within the whole range of old society, assumes
such a violent, glaring character, that
a small section of the ruling class cuts itself
adrift, and joins the revolutionary class, the
class that holds the future in its hands. Just
as, therefore, at an earlier period, a section of
the nobility went over to the bourgeoisie, so
now a portion of the bourgeoisie goes over to
the proletariat, and in particular, a portion of
the bourgeois ideologists, who have raised
themselves to the level of comprehending
theoretically the historical movement as a
whole.
Of all the classes that stand face to face
with the bourgeoisie today, the proletariat
alone is a really revolutionary class. The other
classes decay and finally disappear in the face
of Modern Industry; the proletariat is its special
and essential product.
The lower middle-class, the small manufacturer,
the shopkeeper, the artisan, the
peasant, all these fight against the bourgeoisie,
to save from extinction their existence
as fractions of the middle class. They are
therefore, not revolutionary, but conservative.
Nay, more, they are reactionary, for they try
to roll back the wheel of history. If, by chance
they are revolutionary, they are so, only in
view of their impending transfer into the proletariat,
they thus defend not their present,
but their future interests, they desert their
own standpoint to place themselves at that of
the proletariat.
The "dangerous class", the social scum, that
passively rotting mass thrown off by the lowest
layers of the old society, may, here and there,
be swept into the movement by a proletarian
revolution; its conditions of life, however,
prepare it far more for the part of a bribed
tool of reactionary intrigue.
In the conditions of the proletariat, those
of old society at large are already virtually
swamped. The proletarian is without property;
his relation to his wife and children has
no longer anything in common with the bourgeois
family-relations; modern industry labor,
modern subjection to capital, the same
in England as in France, in America as in
Germany, has stripped him of every trace of
national character. Law, morality, religion,
are to him so many bourgeois prejudices, behind
which lurk in ambush just as many bourgeois
interests.
All the preceding classes that got the upper
hand, sought to fortify their already acquired
status by subjecting society at large to their
conditions of appropriation. The proletarians
cannot become masters of the productive
forces of society, except by abolishing their
own previous mode of appropriation, and
thereby also every other previous mode of
appropriation. They have nothing of their
own to secure and to fortify; their mission is
to destroy all previous securities for, and insurances
of, individual property.
All previous historical movements were
movements of minorities, or in the interests
of minorities. The proletarian movement is
the self-conscious, independent movement of
the immense majority, in the interest of the
immense majority. The proletariat, the lowest
stratum of our present society, cannot stir,
cannot raise itself up, without the whole
superincumbent strata of official society being
sprung into the air.
Though not in substance, yet in form, the
struggle of the proletariat with the bourgeoisie
is at first a national struggle. The proletariat
of each country must, of course, first
of all settle matters with its own bourgeoisie.
In depicting the most general phases of
the development of the proletariat, we traced
the more or less veiled civil war, ranging
within existing society, up to the point where
that war breaks out into open revolution, and
where the violent overthrow of the bourgeoisie
lays the foundation for the sway of
the proletariat.
Hitherto, every form of society has been
based, as we have already seen, on the antagonism
of oppressing and oppressed classes.
But in order to oppress a class, certain conditions
must be assured to it under which it
can, at least, continue its slavish existence.
The serf, in the period of serfdom, raised himself
to membership in the commune, just as
the petty bourgeois, under the yoke of feudal
absolutism, managed to develop into a bourgeois.
The modern laborer, on the contrary, instead
of rising with the process of industry,
sinks deeper and deeper below the conditions
of existence of his own class. He becomes a
pauper, and pauperism develops more rapidly
than population and wealth. And here it becomes
evident that the bourgeoisie is unfit
any longer to be the ruling class in society,
and to impose its conditions of existence upon
society as an over-riding law. It is unfit to
rule, because it is incompetent to assure an
existence to its slave within his slavery, because
it cannot help letting him sink into such
a state that it has to feed him, instead of being
fed by him. Society can no longer live under
this bourgeoisie, in other words, its existence
is no longer compatible with society.
The essential conditions for the existence,
and for the sway of the bourgeois class, is the
formation and augmentation of capital; the
condition for capital is wage-labor. Wage-labor
rests exclusively on competition between
the laborers. The advance of industry,
whose involuntary promoter is the bourgeoisie,
replaces the isolation of the laborers,
due to competition, by the revolutionary
combination, due to association. The development
of Modern Industry, therefore, cuts
from under its feet the very foundation on
which the bourgeoisie produces and appropriates
products. What the bourgeoisie therefore
produces, above all, are its own grave-diggers.
Its fall and the victory of the proletariat
are equally inevitable.
II
Proletarians and Communists
In what relation do the Communists stand
to the proletarians as a whole?
The Communists do not form a separate
party opposed to the other working-class parties.
They have no interests separate and apart
from those of the proletariat as a whole.
They do not set up any sectarian principles
of their own, by which to shape and mould
the proletarian movement.
The Communists are distinguished from
the other working-class parties by this only:
1. In the national struggles of the proletarians
of the different countries, they point out and
bring to the front the common interests of
the entire proletariat independently of all
nationality.
2. In the various stages of development
which the struggle of the working
class against the bourgeoisie has to pass
through, they always and everywhere represent
the interests of the movement as a whole.
The Communists, therefore, are on the one
hand, practically, the most advanced and
resolute section of the working-class parties
of every country, that section which pushes
forward all others; on the other hand, theoretically,
they have over the great mass of
the proletariat the advantage of clearly understanding
the lines of march, the conditions,
and the ultimate general results of the proletarian
movement.
The immediate aim of the Communists is
the same as that of all other proletarian
parties: Formation of the proletariat into a
class, overthrow of the bourgeois supremacy,
conquest of political power by the proletariat.
The theoretical conclusions of the Communists
are in no way based on ideas or
principles that have been invented, or discovered,
by this or that would-be universal
reformer.
They merely express, in general terms, actual
relations springing from an existing class
struggle, from a historical movement going
on under our very eyes. The abolition of existing
property relations is not at all a distinctive
feature of Communism.
All property relations in the past have continually
been subject to historical change
consequent upon the change in historical conditions.
The French Revolution, for example, abolished
feudal property in favor of bourgeois
property.
The distinguishing feature of Communism
is not the abolition of property generally, but
the abolition of bourgeois property. But modern
bourgeois private property is the final and
most complete expression of the system of
producing and appropriating products, that
is based on class antagonisms, on the exploitation
of the many by the few.
In this sense, the theory of the Communists
may be summed up in the single sentence:
Abolition of private property.
We Communists have been reproached
with the desire of abolishing the right of
personally acquiring property as the fruit of
a man's own labor, which property is alleged
to be the groundwork of all personal freedom,
activity and independence.
Hard-won, self-acquired, self-earned property!
Do you mean the property of the petty
artisan and of the small peasant, a form of
property that preceded the bourgeois form?
There is no need to abolish that; the development
of industry has to a great extent already
destroyed it, and is still destroying it daily.
Or do you mean the modern bourgeois private
property?
But does wage-labor create any property
for the laborer? Not a bit. It creates capital,
i.e., that kind of property which exploits
wage-labor, and which cannot increase except
upon conditions of getting a new supply of
wage-labor for fresh exploitation. Property,
in its present form, is based on the antagonism
of capital and wage-labor. Let us examine
both sides of this antagonism.
To be a capitalist, is to have not only a
purely personal, but a social status in production.
Capital is a collective product, and only
by the united action of many members, nay,
in the last resort, only by the united action of
all members of society, can it be set in motion.
Capital is therefore not only personal; it is a
social power.
When, therefore, capital is converted into
common property, into the property of all
members of society, personal property is not
thereby transformed into social property. It is
only the social character of the property that
is changed. It loses its class-character.
Let us now take wage-labor.
The average price of wage-labor is the minimum
wage, i.e., that quantum of the means
of subsistence, which is absolutely requisite
to keep the laborer in bare existence as a laborer.
What, therefore, the wage-laborer appropriates
by means of his labor, merely
suffices to prolong and reproduce a bare existence.
We by no means intend to abolish this
personal appropriation of the products of labor,
an appropriation that is made for the
maintenance and reproduction of human life,
and that leaves no surplus wherewith to command
the labor of others. All that we want to
do away with is the miserable character of
this appropriation, under which the laborer
lives merely to increase capital, and is allowed
to live only in so far as the interest of
the ruling class requires it.
In bourgeois society, living labor is but a
means to increase accumulated labor. In
Communist society, accumulated labor is but
a means to widen, to enrich, to promote the
existence of the laborer.
In bourgeois society, therefore, the past
dominates the present; in Communist society,
the present dominates the past. In bourgeois
society, capital is independent and has individuality,
while the living person is dependent
and has no individuality.
And the abolition of this state of things is
called by the bourgeois, abolition of individuality
and freedom! And rightly so. The
abolition of bourgeois individuality, bourgeois
freedom is undoubtedly aimed at.
By freedom is meant, under the present
bourgeois conditions of production, free
trade, free selling and buying.
But if selling and buying disappears, free
selling and buying disappears also. This talk
about free selling and buying, and all the
other "brave words" of our bourgeoisie about
freedom in general, have a meaning, if any,
only in contrast with restricted selling and
buying, with the fettered traders of the Middle
Ages, but have no meaning when opposed
to the Communist abolition of buying and
selling, of the bourgeois conditions of production,
and of the bourgeoisie itself.
You are horrified at our intending to do
away with private property. But in your existing
society, private property is already done
away with for nine-tenths of the population;
its existence for the few is solely due to its
non-existence in the hands of those nine-tenths.
You reproach us, therefore, with intending
to do away with a form of property,
the necessary condition for whose existence
is, the non-existence of any property for the
immense majority of society.
In one word, you reproach us with intending
to do away with your property. Precisely
so; that is just what we intend.
From the moment when labor can no
longer be converted into capital, money, or
rent, into a social power capable of being
monopolized, i.e., from the moment when
individual property can no longer be transformed
into bourgeois property, into capital,
from that moment, you say, individuality
vanishes.
You must, therefore, confess that by "individual"
you mean no other person than the
bourgeois, than the middle-class owner of
property. This person must, indeed, be swept
out of the way, and made impossible.
Communism deprives no man of the power
to appropriate the products of society: all
that it does is to deprive him of the power
to subjugate the labor of others by means of
such appropriation.
It has been objected, that upon the abolition
of private property all work will cease,
and universal laziness will overtake us.
According to this, bourgeois society ought
long ago to have gone to the dogs through
sheer idleness; for those of its members who
work, acquire nothing, and those who acquire
anything, do not work. The whole of this
objection is but another expression of the
tautology: that there can no longer be any
wage-labor when there is no longer any capital.
All objections urged against the Communistic
mode of producing and appropriating
material products, have, in the same way,
been urged against the Communistic modes
of producing and appropriating intellectual
products. Just as, to the bourgeois, the disappearance
of class property is the disappearance
of production itself, so the disappearance
of class culture is to him identical with
the disappearance of all culture.
That culture, the loss of which he laments,
is, for the enormous majority, a mere training
to act as a machine.
But don't wrangle with us so long as you
apply, to our intended abolition of bourgeois
property, the standard of your bourgeois notions
of freedom, culture, law, etc. Your very
ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions
of your bourgeois production and bourgeois
property, just as your jurisprudence is but the
will of your class made into a law for all, a
will, whose essential character and direction
are determined by the economical conditions
of existence of your class.
The selfish misconception that induces you
to transform into eternal laws of nature and
of reason, the social forms stringing from your
present mode of production and form of property -
historical relations that rise and disappear
in the progress of production - this
misconception you share with every ruling
class that has preceded you. What you see
clearly in the case of ancient property, what
you admit in the case of feudal property, you
are of course forbidden to admit in the case
of your own bourgeois form of property.
Abolition of the family! Even the most
radical flare up at this infamous proposal of
the Communists.
On what foundation is the present family,
the bourgeois family, based? On capital, on
private gain. In its completely developed
form this family exists only among the bourgeoisie.
But this state of things finds its complement
in the practical absence of the family
among the proletarians, and in public prostitution.
The bourgeois family will vanish as a matter
of course when its complement vanishes,
and both will vanish with the vanishing of
capital.
Do you charge us with wanting to stop the
exploitation of children by their parents? To
this crime we plead guilty.
But, you will say, we destroy the most hallowed
of relations, when we replace home
education by social.
And your education! Is not that also social,
and determined by the social conditions under
which you educate, by the intervention,
direct or indirect, of society by means of
schools, etc.? The Communists have not invended
the intervention of society in education;
they do but seek to alter the character
of that intervention, and to rescue education
from the influence of the ruling class.
The bourgeois clap-trap about the family
and education, about the hallowed co-relation
of parents and child, becomes all the more
disgusting, the more, by the action of Modern
Industry, all the family ties among the proletarians
are torn asunder, and their children transformed
into simple articles of commerce and
instruments of labor.
But you Communists would introduce community
of women, screams the bourgeoisie
in chorus.
The bourgeois sees in his wife a mere instrument
of production. He hears that the
instruments of production are to be exploited
in common, and, naturally, can come to no
other conclusion, that the lot of being
common to all will likewise fall to the women.
He has not even a suspicion that the real
point aimed at is to do away with the status
of women as mere instruments of production.
For the rest, nothing is more ridiculous
than the virtuous indignation of our bourgeois
at the community of women which, they pretend,
is to be openly and officially established
by the Communists. The Communists have
no need to introduce community of women;
it has existed almost from time immemorial.
Our bourgeois, not content with having the
wives and daughters of their proletarians at
their disposal, not to speak of common prostitutes,
take the greatest pleasure in seducing
each other's wives.
Bourgeois marriage is in reality a system of
wives in common and thus, at the most, what
the Communists might possibly be reproached
with, is that they desire to introduce,
in substitution for a hypocritically concealed,
an openly legalized community of
women. For the rest, it is self-evident, that
the abolition of the present system of production
must bring with it the abolition of the
community of women springing from that
system, i.e., of prostitution both public and
private.
The Communists are further reproached
with desiring to abolish countries and nationalities.
The working men have no country. We cannot
take away from them what they have not
got. Since the proletariat must first of all acquire
political supremacy, must rise to be the
leading class of the nation, must constitute
itself the nation, it is, so far, itself national,
though not in the bourgeois sense of the
word.
National differences, and antagonisms between
peoples, are daily more and more vanishing,
owing to the development of the bourgeoisie,
to freedom of commerce, to the
world-market, to uniformity in the mode of
production and in the conditions of life corresponding
thereto.
The supremacy of the proletariat will cause
them to vanish still faster. United action, of
the leading civilized countries at least, is one
of the first conditions for the emancipation
of the proletariat.
In proportion as the exploitation of one
individual by another is put an end to, the
exploitation of one nation by another will
also be put an end to. In proportion as the
antagonism between classes within the nation
vanishes, the hostility of one nation to another
will come to an end.
The charges against Communism made
from a religious, a philosophical, and, generally,
from an ideological standpoint, are not
deserving of serious examination.
Does it require deep intuition to comprehend
that man's ideas, views, and conceptions,
in one word, man's consciousness,
changes with every change in the condition
of his material existence, in his social relations
and in his social life?
What else does the history of ideas prove,
than that intellectual production changes in
character in proportion as material production
is changed? The ruling ideas of each age
have ever been the ideas of its ruling class.
When people speak of ideas that revolutionize
society, they do but express that fact,
that within the old society, the elements of
a new one have been created, and that the
dissolution of the old ideas keeps even pace
with the dissolution of the old conditions of
existence.
When the ancient world was in its last
throes, the ancient religions were overcome by
Christianity. When Christian ideas succumbed
in the 18th century to rationalist
ideas, feudal society fought its death-battle
with the then revolutionary bourgeoisie. The
ideas of religious liberty and freedom of conscience,
merely gave expression to the sway
of free competition within the domain of
knowledge.
"Undoubtedly," it will be said, "religious,
moral, philosophical, and juridicial ideas have
been modified in the course of historical development.
But religion, morality, philosophy,
political science, and law, constantly
survived this change.
"There are, besides, eternal truths, such as
Freedom, Justice, etc., that are common to all
states of society. But Communism abolishes
eternal truths, it abolishes all religion, and
all morality, instead of constituting them on
a new basis; it therefore acts in contradiction
to all past historical experience."
What does this accusation reduce itself to?
The history of all past society has consisted in
the development of class antagonisms, antagonisms
that assumed different forms at
different epochs.
But whatever form they may have taken,
one fact is common to all past ages, viz., the
exploitation of one part of society by another.
No wonder, then, that the social consciousness
of past ages, despite all the multiplicity and
variety it displays, moves within certain common
forms, or general ideas, which cannot
completely vanish except with the total disappearance
of class antagonisms.
The Communist revolution is the most radical
rupture with traditional property-relations;
no wonder that its development involves
the most radical rupture with traditional
ideas.
We have seen above, that the first step in
the revolution by the working class, is to raise
the proletariat to the position of ruling class,
to win the battle of democracy.
The proletariat will use its political supremacy,
to wrest, by degrees, all capital from
the bourgeoisie, to centralize all instruments
of production in the hands of the State, i.e.,
of the proletariat organized as the ruling
class; and to increase the total of productive
forces as rapidly as possible.
Of course, in the beginning, this cannot be
effected except by means of despotic inroads
on the rights of property, and on the conditions
of bourgeois production, by means of
measures, therefore, which appear economically
insufficient and untenable, but which,
in the course of the movement, outstrip themselves,
necessitate further inroads upon the
old social order, and are unavoidable as a
means of entirely revolutionizing the mode
of production.
These measures will of course be different
in different countries.
Nevertheless, in most advanced countries
the following will be pretty generally
applicable:
1. Abolition of property in land and application
of all rents of land to public purposes.
2. A heavy progressive or graduated income
tax.
3. Abolition of all rights of inheritance.
4. Confiscation of the property of all emigrants
and rebels.
5. Centralization of credit in the hands of
the State, by means of a national bank with
State capital and an exclusive monopoly.
6. Centralization of the means of communication
and transport in he hands of the State.
7. Extension of factories and instruments
of production owned by the State, the bringing
into cultivation of waste lands, and the
improvement of the soil generally in accordance
with a common plan.
8. Equal liability of all to labor. Establishment
of industrial armies, especially for agriculture.
9. Combination of agriculture with manufacturing
industries; gradual abolition of the
distinction between town and country, by a
more equable distribution of population over
the country.
10. Free education for all children in public
schools. Abolition of children's factory labor
in its present form. Combination of education
with industrial production, etc., etc.
When, in the course of development, class
distinctions have disappeared, and all production
has been concentrated in the hands
of a vast association of the whole nation, the
public power will lose its political character.
Political power, properly so called, is merely
the organized power of one class for suppressing
another. If the proletariat during its contest
with the bourgeoisie is compelled, by the
force of circumstances, to organize itself as
a class, if, by means of a revolution, it makes
itself the ruling class, and, as such, sweeps
away by force the old conditions of production,
then it will, along with these conditions,
have swept away the conditions for the existence
of class antagonisms, and of classes generally,
and will thereby have abolished its
own supremacy as a class.
In place of the old bourgeois society, with
its classes and class antagonisms, we shall
have an association, in which the free development
of each is the condition for the free
development of all.
III
Socialist and Communist Literature
1. Reactionary Socialism
2. Feudal Socialism
Owing to their historical position, it became
the vocation of the aristocracies of France
and England to write pamphlets against modern
bourgeois society. In the French revolution
of July, 1830, and in the English reform
agitation, these aristocracies again succumbed
to the hateful upstart. Thenceforth, a serious
political conquest was altogether out of the
question. A literary battle alone remained
possible. But even in the domain of literature
the old cries of the restoration period
had become impossible.
In order to arouse sympathy, the aristocracy
was obliged to lose sight, apparently,
of their own interests, and to formulate their
indictment against the bourgeoisie in the interest
of the exploited working class alone.
Thus the aristocracy took their revenge by
singing lampoons on their new masters, and
whispering in his ears sinister prophesies of
coming catastrophe.
In this way arose feudal socialism: half
lamentation, half lampoon; half an echo of the
past, half menace of the future; at times, by
its bitter, witty and incisive criticism, striking
the bourgeoisie to the very hearts' core,
but always ludicrous in its effect, through
total incapacity to comprehend the march of
modern history.
The aristocracy, in order to rally the people
to them, waved the proletarian alms-bag in
front for a banner. But the people, so often as
it joined them, saw on their hindquarters the
old feudal coats of arms, and deserted with
loud and irreverent laughter.
One section of the French Legitimists, and
"Young England" exhibited this spectacle.
In pointing out that their mode of exploitation
was different to that of the bourgeoisie,
the feudalists forget that they exploited under
circumstances and conditions that were
quite different, and that are now antiquated.
In showing that, under their rule, the modern
proletariat never existed, they forget that the
modern bourgeoisie is the necessary offspring
of their own form of society.
For the rest, so little do they conceal the
reactionary character of their criticism, that
their chief accusation against the bourgeois
amounts to this, that under the bourgeoisie
regime a class is being developed, which is
destined to cut up root and branch the old
order of society.
What they upbraid the bourgeoisie with is
not so much that it creates a proletariat, as
that it creates a revolutionary proletariat.
In political practice, therefore, they join in
all coercive measures against the working-class;
and in ordinary life, despite their high-falutin
phrases, they stoop to pick up the
golden apples dropped from the tree of industry,
and to barter truth, love, and honor, for
traffic in wool, beet-root sugar and potato
spirits.
As the parson has ever gone hand in hand
with the landlord, so has Clerical Socialism
with Feudal Socialism.
Nothing is easier than to give Christian
asceticism a Socialist tinge. Has not Christianity
declaimed against private property,
against marriage, against the State? Has it not
preached in the place of these, charity and
poverty, celibacy and mortification of the
flesh, monastic life and Mother Church?
Christian Socialism is but the Holy Water
with which the priest consecrates the heart-burnings
of the aristocrat.
Petty-Bourgeois Socialism
The feudal aristocracy was not the only
class that was ruined by the bourgeoisie, not
the only class whose conditions of existence
pined and perished in the atmosphere of
modern bourgeois society. The medieval burgesses
and the small peasant bourgeoisie,
were the precursors of the modern bourgeoisie.
In those countries which are but
little developed, industrially and commercially,
these two classes still vegetate side by
side with the rising bourgeoisie.
In countries where modern civilization has
become fully developed, a new class of petty
bourgeois has been formed, fluctuating between
proletariat and bourgeoisie, and ever
renewing itself a supplementary part of
bourgeoisie society. The individual members
of this class, however, as being constantly
hurled down into the proletariat by the action
of competition, and, as modern industry develops,
they can see the moment approaching
when they will completely disappear as an
independent section of modern society, to be
replaced, in manufacture, agriculture and
commerce, by over-lookers, bailiffs and shopmen.
In countries like France, where the peasants
constitute far more than half of the population,
it was natural that writers who sided
with the proletariat against the bourgeoisie,
should use, in their criticism of the bourgeoisie
regime, the standard of the peasant
and petty bourgeois, and from the standpoint
of these intermediate classes, should take up
the cudgels for the working class. Thus arose
petty bourgeois Socialism. Sismondi was the
head of this school, not only in France, but
also in England.
This school of Socialism dissected with
great acuteness the contradictions in the conditions
of modern production. It laid bare the
hypocritical apologies of economists. It
proved, incontrovertibly, the disastrous effects
of machinery and division of labor; the
concentration of capital and land in a few
hands; overproduction and crises; it pointed
out the inevitable ruin of the petty bourgeois
and peasant, the misery of the proletariat, the
anarchy in production, the crying inequalities
in the distribution of wealth, the industrial
war of extermination between nations, the
dissolution of old moral bonds, of the old
family relations, of the old nationalities.
In it positive aims, however, this form of
Socialism aspires either to restoring the old
means of production and of exchange, and
with them the old property relations, and the
old society, or to cramping the modern means
of production and of exchange, within the
framework of the old property relations that
have been, and were bound to be exploded
by those means. In either case, it is both reactionary
and Utopian.
Its last words are: corporate guilds for
manufacture; patriarchal relations in agriculture.
Ultimately, when stubborn historical facts
had dispersed all intoxicating effects of self-deception,
this form of Socialism ended in a
miserable fit of the blues.
German or "True" Socialism
The Socialist and Communist literature
of France, a literature that originated under the
pressure of a bourgeoisie in power, and that
was the expression of the struggle against this
power, was introduced into Germany at a
time when the bourgeoisie, in that country,
had just begun its contest with feudal absolutism.
German philosophers, would-be philosophers,
and beaux esprits, eagerly seized on
this literature, only forgetting, that when
these writings immigrated from France into
Germany, French social conditions had not
immigrated along with them. In contact with
German social conditions, this French literature
lost all its immediate practical significance
and assumed a purely literary aspect.
Thus, to the German philosophers of the
Eighteenth Century, the demands of the first
French Revolution were nothing more than
the demands of "Practical Reason" in general,
and the utterance of the will of the revolutionary
French bourgeoisie signified in their
eyes the laws of pure Will, of Will as it was
bound to be, of true human Will generally.
The work of the German literati consisted
solely in bringing the new French ideas into
harmony with their ancient philosophical
conscience, or rather, in annexing the French
ideas without deserting their own philosophical
point of view.
This annexation took place in the same way
in which a foreign language is appropriated,
namely by translation.
It is well known how the monks wrote silly
lives of Catholic Saints over the manuscripts
on which the classical works of ancient heathendom
had been written. The German literati
reversed this process with the profane
French literature. They wrote their philosophical
nonsense beneath the French original.
For instance, beneath the French criticism
of the economic functions of money,
they wrote "Alienation of Humanity," and beneath
the French criticism of the bourgeois
State they wrote, "Dethronement of the Category
of the General," and so forth.
The introduction of these philosophical
phrases at the back of the French historical
criticisms they dubbed "Philosophy of Action,"
"True Socialism," "German Science of
Socialism," "Philosophical Foundation of Socialism,"
and so on.
The French Socialist and Communist literature
was thus completely emasculated. And,
since it ceased in the hands of the German to
express the struggle of one class with the
other, he felt conscious of having overcome
"French one-sidedness" and of representing,
not true requirements, but the requirements
of Truth, not the interests of the proletariat,
but the interests of Human Nature, of Man
in general, who belongs to no class, has no
reality, who exists only in the misty realm of
philosophical phantasy.
This German Socialism, which took its
school-boy task so seriously and solemnly, and
extolled its poor stock-in-trade in such a mountebank
fashion, meanwhile gradually lost its
pedantic innocence.
The fight of the Germans, and especially, of
the Prussian bourgeoisie, against feudal aristocracy
and absolute monarchy, in other
words, the liberal movement, became more
earnest.
By this, the long-wished for opportunity
was offered to "True Socialism" of confronting
the political movement with the socialist
demands, of hurling the traditional anathemas
against liberalism, against representative
government, against bourgeois competition,
bourgeois freedom of the press, bourgeois
legislation, bourgeois liberty and equality,
and of preaching to the masses that they had
nothing to gain, and everything to lose, by
this bourgeois movement. German Socialism
forgot, in the nick of time, that the French
criticism, whose silly echo it was, presupposed
the existence of modern bourgeois society,
with its corresponding economic conditions,
and the political constitution adapted thereto,
the very things those attainment was the
object of the pending struggle in Germany.
To the absolute governments, with their
following of parsons, professors, country
squires, and officials, it served as a welcome
scarecrow against the threatening bourgeoisie.
It was a sweet finish after the bitter pills of
flogging and bullets, with which these same
governments, just at that time, dosed the
German working-class risings.
While this "True" Socialism thus served
the government as a weapon for fighting the
German bourgeoisie, it, at the same time,
directly represented a reactionary interest,
the interest of German Philistines. In Germany,
the petty bourgeois class, a relic of
the 16th century, and since then constantly
cropping up again under the various forms, is
the real social basis of the existing state of
things.
To preserve this class, is to preserve the
existing state of things in Germany. The industrial
and political supremacy of the bourgeoisie
threatens it with certain destruction;
on the one hand, from the concentration of
capital; on the other, from the rise of a revolutionary
proletariat. "True" Socialism appeared
to kill these two birds with one stone. It
spread like an epidemic.
The robe of speculative cobwebs, embroidered
with flowers of rhetoric, steeped in the
dew of sickly sentiment, this transcendental
robe in which the German Socialists wrapped
their sorry "eternal truths," all skin and bone,
served to wonderfully increase the sale of
their goods amongst such a public.
And on its part, German Socialism recognized,
more and more, its own calling as the
bombastic representative of the petty bourgeois
Philistine.
It proclaimed the German nation to be the
model nation, and the German petty Philistine
to be the typical man. To every villainous
meanness of this model man it gave a
hidden, higher socialistic interpretation, the
exact contrary of its real character. It went
to the extreme length of directly opposing the
"brutally destructive" tendency of Communism,
and of proclaiming its supreme and
impartial contempt of all class struggles. With
very few exceptions, all the so-called Socialist
and Communist publications that now (1847)
circulate in Germany belong to the domain
of this foul and enervating literature.
Conservative or Bourgeois Socialism
A part of the bourgeoisie is desirous of redressing
social grievances, in order to secure
the continued existence of bourgeois society.
To this section belong economists, philanthropists,
humanitarians, improvers of the
condition of the working class, organizers of
charity, members of societies for the prevention
of cruelty to animals, temperance fanatics,
hole and corner reformers of every imaginable
kind. This form of Socialism has,
moreover, been worked out into complete
systems.
We may cite Proudhon's "Philosophie de
la Misere" as an example of this form.
The socialistic bourgeois want all the advantages
of modern social conditions without
the struggles and dangers necessarily resulting
therefrom. They desire the existing state
of society minus its revolutionary and disintegrating
elements. They wish for a bourgeoisie
without a proletariat. The bourgeoisie
naturally conceives the world in which it is
supreme to be the best; and bourgeois socialism
develops this comfortable conception into
various more or less complete systems. In
requiring the proletariat to carry out such a
system, and thereby to march straightaway
into the social New Jerusalem, it but requires
in reality, that the proletariat should remain
within the bounds of existing society, but
should cast away all its hateful ideas concerning
the bourgeoisie.
A second and more practical, but less systematic,
form of this socialism sought to depreciate
every revolutionary movement in the
eyes of the working class, by showing that no
mere political reform, but only a change in the
material conditions of existence, in economical
relations, could be of any advantage to
them. By changes in the material conditions
of existence, this form of Socialism, however,
by no means understands abolition of the
bourgeois relations of production, an abolition
that can be effected only by a revolution,
but administrative reforms, based on the continued
existence of these relations; reforms,
therefore, that in no respect affect the relations
between capital and labor, but, at the
best, lessen the cost, and simplify the administrative
work, of bourgeois government.
Bourgeois Socialism attains adequate expression,
when, and only when, it becomes a
mere figure of speech.
Free trade: for the benefit of the working
class. Protective duties: for the benefit of the
working class. Prison Reform: for the benefit
of the working class. This is the last word and
the only seriously meant word of bourgeois
Socialism.
It is summed up in the phrase: the bourgeois
is a bourgeois - for the benefit of the
working class.
Critical-Utopian Socialism and Communism
We do not here refer to that literature
which, in every great modern revolution, has
always given voice to the demands of the
proletariat: such as the writings of Babeuf
and others.
The first direct attempts of the proletariat
to attain its own ends were made in times of
universal excitement, when feudal society
was being overthrown. These attempts necessarily
failed, owing to the then undeveloped
state of the proletariat, as well as to the absence
of the economic conditions for its emancipation,
conditions that had yet to be produced by the impending bourgeois epoch
alone. The revolutionary literature that accompanied
these first movements of the proletariat
had necessarily a reactionary character.
It inculcated universal asceticism and
social leveling in its crudest form.
The Socialist and Communist systems properly
so-called, those of St. Simon, Fourier,
Owen and others, spring into existence in
the early undeveloped period, described
above, of the struggle between proletariat
and bourgeoisie (see Section I, Bourgeois and
Proletarians).
The founders of these systems see, indeed,
the class antagonisms, as well as the action
of the decomposing elements in the prevailing
form of society. But the proletariat, as yet
in its infancy, offers to them the spectacle of
a class without any historical initiative or any
independent political movement.
Since the development of class antagonism
keeps even pace with the development of industry,
the economic situation, as they find
it, does not as yet offer to them the material
conditions for the emancipation of the proletariat.
They therefore search after a new social
science, after new social laws, that are to
create these conditions.
Historical action is to yield to their personal
inventive action; historically created
conditions of emancipation to fantastic ones,
and the gradual, spontaneous class-organization
of the proletariat to an organization of
society specially contrived by these inventors.
Future history resolves itself, in their eyes,
into the propaganda and the practical carrying
out of their social plans.
In the formation of their plans they are
conscious of caring chiefly for the interests of
the working-class, as being the most suffering
class. Only from the point of view of being
the most suffering class does the proletariat
exist for them.
The undeveloped state of the class struggle,
as well as their own surroundings, causes Socialists
of this kind to consider themselves far
superior to all class antagonisms. They want
to improve the condition of every member of
society, even that of the most favored. Hence,
they habitually appeal to society at large,
without the distinction of class; nay, by preference,
to the ruling class. For how can people,
when once they understand their system,
fail to see in it the best possible plan of the
best possible state of society?
Hence, they reject all political, and especially
all revolutionary action; they wish to
attain their ends by peaceful means, and endeavor,
by small experiments, necessarily
doomed to failure, and by the force of example,
to pave the way for the new social
Gospel.
Such fantastic pictures of future society,
painted at a time when the proletariat is still
in a very undeveloped state, and has but a
fantastic conception of its own position, correspond
with the first instinctive yearnings
of that class for a general reconstruction of
society.
But these Socialist and Communist publications
contain also a critical element. They attack
every principle of existing society. Hence they
are full of the most valuable materials for the
enlightenment of the working class. The practical
measures proposed in them, such as the
abolition of the distinction between town and
country, of the family, of the carrying on of
industries for the account of private individuals,
and of the wage system, the proclamation
of social harmony, the conversion of the
functions of the State into a more superintendence
of production, all these proposals
point solely to the disappearance of class-antagonisms
which were, at that time, only
just cropping up, and which, in these publications,
are recognized in their earliest,
indistinct and undefined forms only. These
proposals, therefore, are of a purely utopian
character.
The significance of Critical-Utopian Socialism
and Communism bears an inverse
relation to historical development. In proportion
as the modern class struggle develops
and takes definite shape, this fantastic standing
apart from the contest, these fantastic
attacks on it lose all practical value and all
theoretical justification. Therefore, although
the originators of these systems were, in many
respects, revolutionary, their disciples have, in
every case, formed mere reactionary sects.
They hold fast by the original views of their
masters, in opposition to the progressive historical
development of the proletariat. They
therefore endeavor, and that consistently, to
deaden the class struggle and to reconcile the
class antagonisms. They still dream of experimental
relations of their social Utopias,
of founding isolated "phalansteres," of establishing
"Home Colonies," or setting up a
"Little Icaria" - duodecimo editions of the
New Jerusalem, and to realize all these castles
in the air, they are compelled to appeal to the
feelings and purses of the bourgeois. By degrees,
they sink into the category of the
reactionary conservative Socialists depicted
above, differing from these only by more
systematic pedantry, and by their fanatical
and superstitious belief in the miraculous effects
of their social science.
They, therefore, violently oppose all political
action on the part of the working class;
such action, according to them, can only result
from blind unbelief in the new Gospel.
The Owenites in England, and the Fourierists
in France, respectively, oppose the
Chartists and the "Reformists."
IV
Position of the Communists in Relation to
the Various Existing Opposition Parties
Section II has made clear the relations of the
Communists to the existing working-class
parties, such as the Chartists in England and
the Agrarian Reformers in America.
The Communists fight for the attainment
of the immediate aims, for the enforcement of
the momentary interests of the working class;
but in the movement of the present, they also
represent and take care of the future of that
movement. In France the Communists ally
themselves with the Social-Democrats,
against the conservatives and radical bourgeoisie,
reserving, however, the rights to take
up a critical position in regard to phases and
illusions traditionally handed down from the
great Revolution.
In Switzerland, they support the Radicals,
without losing sight of the fact that this party
consists of antagonistic elements, partly of
Democratic Socialists, in the French sense,
partly of radical bourgeois.
In Poland they support the party that insists
on an agrarian revolution, as the prime
condition for national emancipation, that
party which fomented the insurrection of
Crakow in 1846.
In Germany they fight with the bourgeoisie
whenever it acts in a revolutionary way,
against the absolute monarchy, the feudal
squirearchy, and the petty bourgeoisie.
But they never cease, for a single instant,
to instill into the working class the clearest
possible recognition of the hostile antagonism
between bourgeoisie and proletariat, in order
that the German workers may straightway
use, as so many weapons against the bourgeoisie,
the social and political conditions
that the bourgeoisie must necessarily introduce
along with its supremacy, and in order
that, after the fall of the reactionary classes
in Germany, the fight against the bourgeoisie
itself may immediately begin.
The Communists turn their attention
chiefly to Germany, because that country is
on the eve of a bourgeois revolution, that is
bound to be carried out under more advanced
conditions of European civilization, and with
a more developed proletariat, than that of
England was in the seventeenth, and of
France in the eighteenth century, and because
the bourgeois revolution in Germany
will be but the prelude to an immediately
following proletarian revolution.
In short, the Communists everywhere support
every revolutionary movement against
the existing social and political order of
things.
In all these movements they bring to the
front, as the leading question in each, the
property question, no matter what its degree
of development at the time.
Finally, they labor everywhere for the
union and agreement of the democratic
parties of all countries.
The Communists disdain to conceal their
views and aims. They openly declare that
their ends can be attained only by the forcible
overthrow of all existing social conditions.
Let the ruling classes tremble at a Communist
revolution. The proletarians have nothing
to lose but their chains. They have a world to
win.
Working men of all countries, unite!